Amanpulo, Palawan, Philippines |
It is difficult indeed
to make conclusions if one does not have a clear basis from which to conclude,
just like in the case of the epistemology of Aristotle or how Aristotle
understood episteme. There have been
a lot of interpretations regarding this matter. The Greek philosopher did not
leave any particular work that deals especially with this, as C.C.W. Taylor confirmed: “In contrast with Plato,
none of Aristotle’s major works has its central topic the nature of knowledge
in general.”[1]
In Posterior Analytics we may find some discussions about this topic of
knowledge, but here Aristotle drew a number of distinctions and the liberal use
of terms that spur debates until the present day.
I.
ΕΠΙΣΤΕΜΕ: A SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE?
Caramoan, Camarines Sur, Philippines |
What is ἐπιστήμη to
Aristotle? Among the modern commentators of Aristotle, many understand it as
“scientific knowledge” while others, like Burnyeat, consider it as some special
cognitive state or “understanding” as opposed to a simple knowledge. What is the difference between “scientific
knowledge” and “understanding” then? The Greek term ἐπιστήμη which Aristotle
himself was analyzing, according to Burnyeat, can refer either to the cognitive
state of the knowing person or to a body of knowledge or a science- a system of propositions which can
be learned and known.[2] Many
Aristotelian commentators, like Taylor, translate this term as “scientific
knowledge.” Scientific knowledge is a knowledge accumulated by systematic study
and organized by general principles. It is usually attained by demonstration.
Biology, for example, is a scientific knowledge or science about the living
things especially with reference to their origin, growth, reproduction,
structure, and behavior. It may answer questions like: Why do horses sleep
standing up? The acquisition of knowledge in this discipline is through
experiments and demonstrations. It does not explain though why they have life,
which is the common principle among living matters. Burnyeat, however, refuted
the traditional English translation of Aristotelian episteme as “scientific knowledge”. According to him, the results
this produces can be ambiguous and puzzling.[3] And
we will know why. And he also emphasizes that there is no Greek word or term
that corresponds to the modern term “scientific”. By scientific we mean
“systematic or accurate in manner”. For
his part, Taylor refuses to translate the Greek terms sophia and nous as
‘wisdom’ and ‘intelligence’ respectively because, according to him, this would
be uninformative, or even worse, misleading. But he does not hesitate to
translate episteme as scientific
knowledge. Burnyeat, as we know, questions this translation.
Unmnamed islet, Cebu, Philippines |
Burnyeat argues that “Aristotle
first advances a quite general thesis about a cognitive state” which the Greek
thinker himself calls ἐπἰστασϑαι, that “in its unqualified version this involves
knowing the cause or explanation of something and knowing its necessity”, and
that from this “one can have ἐπιστήμη of is that which cannot be otherwise.”[4] Burnyeat
distinguishes ἐπἰστασϑαι from ἐπιστήμη. Burnyeat speaks of two phases or modes
of the cognitive state which are distinct but complementary. This will help to clarify the issue. Burnyeat,
moreover, assures that Aristotle gives the main characteristic of the cognitive
state: “it centrally involves the possession of apodeictic proof or
demonstration.”[5]
By apodeictic we mean that is unquestionably or necessarily true. It means that
the cognitive state possesses what is necessarily true.
Bellaroca, Marinduque, Philippines |
He criticizes G.R.G. Mure’s
translation (“the premises of demonstrated knowledge”) for he believes that a
cognitive state cannot be demonstrated nor it has premises. He says that “these
attributes belong to knowledge in the other sense of what is known,” and he
further clarifies, “to the propositions making up the body of science.”[6] We
may understand Burnyeat’s argument in this simple logic: If we suppose that ἐπἰστασϑαι
is a cognitive state, but a cognitive state cannot be demonstrated nor it has
premises, therefore the ἐπἰστασϑαι cannot be demonstrated nor it has premises. In
other words, if we accept this thesis of Burnyeat (“A cognitive state cannot be
said to be demonstrated, nor does it have premises”), therefore the cognitive
state denotes a knowledge that is evident, necessary, and universal. Burnyeat’s
argument, we believe, is very much in line with Aristotle’s idea that there is
no distinction between what one perceives and what is being perceived. The ἐπἰστασϑαι
could consequently mean the act of
knowing itself or the sensory experience that gives us direct and immediate
knowledge of the objects while episteme is
a kind of special cognitive state.
Dimakya, Palawan, Philippines |
What is evident and
necessary does not need any demonstration because a demonstration is given in order
to clarify things. By demonstration we mean an act or circumstance of proving
or being proved conclusively as by reasoning or a show of evidence. What is
evident is clear in itself and does not need any instrument to represent, to
explain, or to prove itself. We say that scientific knowledge is acquired
through demonstration since we need proofs or even empirical experiments like
in the case of experimental sciences. Scientific knowledge then does not delve
on what is evident but tries to impart information through proofs or
demonstrations. Through this, we may understand why Burnyeat says that
demonstration and premises belong to a body of science. We have that common
knowledge, for example, that the sun rises in the east and sets in the west.
This knowledge is evident. It does not need any demonstration. It becomes a
scientific knowledge when we try to explain why this phenomenon happens or occurs.
For this we have a scientific knowledge or a science about the heavenly
objects, the astronomy. He continues explaining, “The things which are true,
primary, etc. are indeed expressed as the premises of demonstration, but the
dependence in question here is the epistemological relation of the cognitive
state to its grounds, not the logical relation of conclusion to premises.” [7] What
he means here is that what is true or necessary is evidence or proof in itself.
Therefore, the thesis of Taylor: “There is no episteme of the principles of knowledge” is correct or true if episteme here refers to scientific
knowledge.
Hundred Islands, Pangasinan, Philippines |
Aristotle opines: “All
instruction given or received by way of argument proceeds from pre-existent
knowledge.”[8]
If knowledge is demonstrative then the premises prior to it are known than it. It
means that the premises are themselves primary, immediate, and prior to. Burnyeat,
thus, asserts: “Demonstrative ἐπιστήμη depends on things which are true,
primary, immediate, better known than and prior to and explanatory of the
conclusion.”[9]
We are quite sure then that Aristotle’s “pre-existent” knowledge does not mean
scientific knowledge. That “pre-existent” knowledge of Aristotle could not be
demonstrated. If it could be demonstrated, then there is another “pre-existent”
knowledge prior to it, and so on and so forth. We will end up in a vicious
cycle. Thus, if all knowledge is demonstrative, then there is no knowledge per
se. If all knowledge needs proof or evidence, then that proof or evidence is
some kind of possession of knowledge or, we say, a “prior” knowledge. We do
agree with Burnyeat’s conclusion: “Because ἐπιστήμη involves grasping the
demonstration of necessary conclusions, it is grounded epistemologically on the
premises of that demonstration.”[10]
We, therefore, assert that not all knowledge is demonstrative.
Sunken Cemetery, Camiguin, Philippines |
Taylor, on the other
hand, asserts that episteme is a
demonstrative state. By this he means that a human being knows when he believes
something and the principles or the premises are known or presented to him. Citing
the Nicomachean Ethics, he states that “what is grasped by episteme is what is demonstrated, and since there have to be first
principles of demonstration, there is no episteme
of the principles of knowledge.[11] To
prove that there is no knowledge or episteme
of the principles of knowledge, Taylor explains that the principles of demonstration cannot be
themselves demonstrated because if ever
there is this possibility, then the principles of demonstration must be known
and must be known other than by demonstration. The inconsistency of Taylor is
this: if we acquire episteme by
demonstration, then we must know beforehand the premises or principles of that
demonstration. If we say that knowledge is acquired through reasoning, then
there must be a demonstration, but the premises themselves are conclusions of the
demonstration. Therefore not all knowledge is demonstrative. We can conclude
then that not all episteme is
scientific.
Tawi-Tawi, Philippines |
Moreover, Taylor
identifies episteme as one of the
theoretical cognitive states together with the sophia. He states that theoretical knowledge is restricted to
knowledge of the universal necessary truths, but later says that demonstrative
knowledge (episteme) is restricted to
what we can explain. But universal necessary truths do not need any
explanation. What is universal and necessary is proof in itself. In the other
part, he says that “… episteme, phronesis, sophia, and nous are
described as ‘those in which we possess the truth and are never mistaken.”[12] It is indeed true that there can be no error
in knowledge of what is evident. The knowledge of what is evident can never
commit any error, since the evidence is the truth itself. Errors or mistakes
could occur in the demonstration. So it would be a mistake to translate episteme as scientific knowledge if this
latter denotes explanation or show of evidence. Scientific knowledge, though
tries to be systematic and accurate, is still prone to error or mistake.
Biology, Chemistry, and other sciences do not necessarily impart truth. The principles of these sciences are
justified through results of experiments which are prone to mistake or error,
therefore, changeable and contingent.
Bucas Grande, Surigao del Sur, Philippines |
In the other part of
his work, Taylor states this: “Aristotle contrasts episteme properly so called (i.e. scientific knowledge) with
perceptual episteme.”[13] But
he insists that only ‘explanatory’ knowledge ( i.e. scientific knowledge ) of a
phenomenon, that is, knowing in the full sense why that phenomenon occurs, is
worthy to be called episteme, or in
his own words, “dignified by the term episteme”[14]
He admits that explanatory knowledge presupposes a prior knowledge, “knowledge that it occurs.” He believes, however,
that this kind of knowledge is incomplete. Its completion comes only when one
has an explanation of the phenomenon. To qualify this acquisition as knowledge,
one must know the explanation of this phenomenon. For him, only when we come to
understand through explanation that we can have a complete knowledge that is
worthy to be called episteme. Taylor,
however, forgets that this kind of knowledge is “perfect” in itself since it is
indubitable and certain. It is a knowledge of what is evident and true.
We oppose Taylor’s
thesis- ‘explanatory’ knowledge (scientific knowledge) is the ‘true’ knowledge-
because this knowledge could not be knowledge at all since it is prone to error
or mistake. In order to be a true knowledge, it must be assured of foregone conclusion,
which the scientific knowledge may not have. We believe that knowledge consists
in knowing being or truth since it is impossible to know what is not.
II.
ΕΠΙΣΤΕΜΕ AS UNDERSTANDING
Boracay, Aklan, Philippines |
Coron, Palawan, Philippines |
III. CONCLUSION
Miniloc, Palawan, Philippines |
Aristotle |
[1]
C.C.W. Taylor, Aristotle’s Epistemology, p.116
[2]
M.F. Burnyeat, Aristotle on Understanding Knowledge, p.97
[3] Op.
cit.
[4]
Op. cit. p.98
[5] Op. cit.
[6]
Op. cit. p.99
[7]
Op. cit. p. 99
[8]
Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, I.1
[9] Op.
cit.
[10] Burnyeat,
p. 99
[11]
C.C.W. Taylor, Aristotle’s Epistemology, p.119
[12]
Op. cit., p.118
[13]
Op. Cit., p.118
[14]
Taylor, p.122
[15] Burnyeat,
p. 101
[16] Op.
cit.
[17]
Op. cit. p. 102
[18] Aristotle’s
Posterior Analytics, Oxford 1975.
[19] Burnyeat,
p. 117
[20]
Op. cit., pp. 117, 118
[21]
Op. cit., p.133
No comments:
Post a Comment